Open Access

Enactivism, Radical Enactivism and Predictive Processing: What is Radical in Cognitive Science?


Cite

Bermúdez, J.L. (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195159691.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Block, N. (1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19–49.10.2307/1522889Search in Google Scholar

Brooks, R. (1995). Intelligence Without Reason. In L. Steels & R. Brooks (Eds.), The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence: Building Embodied, Situated Agents. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Search in Google Scholar

Brooks, R., & Stein, L.A. (1993). Building Brains for Bodies (1439). Retrieved from http://people.csail.mit.edu/brooks/papers/brains.pdfSearch in Google Scholar

Clark, A., & Toribio, A.J. (1994). Doing without representing. Synthese, 10, 401-431.10.1007/BF01063896Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195333213.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2012a). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind 121 (483), 753-771. doi: 10.1093/mind/fzs106.10.1093/mind/fzs106Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2012b). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 36(3), 181–253.10.1017/S0140525X12000477Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2015a). Embodied prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND (7), 1-21. doi: 10.15502/9783958570115.Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2015b). Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190217013.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs 00:0, 1-27. doi:10.1111/nous.12140.10.1111/nous.12140Search in Google Scholar

Clowes, R.W. (2017). The Ipseity Disturbance Theory of Schizophrenia and Predictive Processing. In I. Hipólito, J. Gonçalves, & J. G. Pereira (Eds.), Schizophrenia and Common Sense: explaining madness and social values. : Springer Mind Brain Studies.Search in Google Scholar

Clowes, R.W., & Chrisley, R. (2012). Virtualist Representation. International Journal of Machine Consciousness, 04(02), 503-522.10.1142/S179384301240029XSearch in Google Scholar

Clowes, R.W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation Redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, Special Issue on Representation(Special Issue: Explaining Representation), 26-47.10.1016/j.newideapsych.2015.03.002Search in Google Scholar

Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation-hunger reconsidered. Synthese, 191 (15), 3639-3648.10.1007/s11229-014-0484-4Search in Google Scholar

Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9-21.10.1007/s11245-008-9042-3Search in Google Scholar

Di Paolo, E., & Thompson, E. (2014). The enactive approach. The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition, 68-78.Search in Google Scholar

Fletcher, P. & Frith, C. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews: Neuro-science 10, 48–58.10.1038/nrn2536Search in Google Scholar

Fodor, J. (1981). Representations, Cambridge: MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Fresco, N. (2010). Explaining Computation Without Semantics: Keeping it Simple. Minds and Machines 20(2), 165–181. doi:10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6.10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6Search in Google Scholar

Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 293-301.10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005Search in Google Scholar

Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0199271941.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Gładziejewski, P. (2015). Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese 193, 559–582 doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9.10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9Search in Google Scholar

Haugeland, J. (1990). The intentionality all-stars. Philosophical perspectives, 383-427.10.2307/2214199Search in Google Scholar

Hohwy, J. (2004). Top-down and bottom-up in delusion formation. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11(1), 65-70.10.1353/ppp.2004.0043Search in Google Scholar

Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682737.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Hohwy, J. (2014). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12062.10.1111/nous.12062Search in Google Scholar

Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A. & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition 108(3), 687–701.10.1016/j.cognition.2008.05.010Search in Google Scholar

Hume, D. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature (Second Edition). Sir Lewis Amherst Selby-Bigge, first baronet & P. H. Nidditch (eds.). Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D. (2011). Enactivism: Why be radical. Sehen und Handeln, 21-44.10.1524/9783050062389.21Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D. (2015). REC: Revolution Effected by Clarification. Topoi, 1-15. doi:10.1007/s11245-015-9358-8.10.1007/s11245-015-9358-8Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D., Kirchhoff, M. D., & Abrahamson, D. (2015). The enactive roots of STEM: rethinking educational design in mathematics. Educational Psychology Review, 27(3), 371-389.10.1007/s10648-015-9326-2Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (Forthcoming). Going Radical. Retrieved from https://www.academia.edu/15763822/Going_Radical?auto=download.Search in Google Scholar

Hutto, D.D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521-536.10.1007/s11406-015-9644-0Search in Google Scholar

Kriegel, U. (2002). PANIC Theory and the Prospects for a Representationalist Theory of Phenomenal Consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 15, 55-64.10.1080/09515080120109414Search in Google Scholar

Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139171434.009Search in Google Scholar

Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (1999). Concepts: core readings: Mit Press.Search in Google Scholar

Miłkowski M. (2013). A mechanistic account of computational explanation in cognitive science. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Cooperative Minds: Social Interaction and Group Dynamics, Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society, 3050–3055. Available online at: http://csjarchive.cogsci.rpi.edu/Proceedings/2013/papers/0545/paper0545.pdf.Search in Google Scholar

Miłkowski, M. (2016a). Function and causal relevance of content. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 94-102.10.1016/j.newideapsych.2014.12.003Search in Google Scholar

Miłkowski, M. (2016b). Unification Strategies in Cognitive Science. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 48(61), 13-33.10.1515/slgr-2016-0053Search in Google Scholar

O’Regan, J.K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939-973.10.1017/S0140525X01000115Search in Google Scholar

Piccinini, G. (2006). Computation without Representation. Philosophical Studies 137(2), 205–241. doi:10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4.10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4Search in Google Scholar

Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199658855.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Pitt, D. (2013). Mental Representation. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2013 Edition, URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/mental-representation/>.Search in Google Scholar

Sacks, O. (2012). Hallucinations: Pan Macmillan.Search in Google Scholar

Seth, A.K., Suzuki, K. & Critchley, H.D. (2011). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology 2, 395.Search in Google Scholar

Shoemaker, S. (1994): Identity, Cause, and Mind. Cambridge University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Steels, L. (1997). Constructing and Sharing Perceptual Distinctions. Paper presented at the Proceedings of the European Conference on Machine Learning, Prague. Springer Verlag, Berlin.10.1007/3-540-62858-4_68Search in Google Scholar

Steels, L., & Belpaeme, T. (2005). Coordinating Perceptually Grounded Categories through Language: A Case Study for Colour. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 469-489.10.1017/S0140525X05000087Search in Google Scholar

Stich, S. (1983). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. The MIT Press.Search in Google Scholar

Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691186672Search in Google Scholar

Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6730.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Watson, J.B. (1913). Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it. Psychological Review 20, 158-177.10.1037/h0074428Search in Google Scholar

eISSN:
1647-659X
Language:
English
Publication timeframe:
3 times per year
Journal Subjects:
Philosophy, Metaphysics, Ontology, Epistemology, Philosophy of Science